Tideman alternative method

Single-winner electoral system family
Part of the Politics series
Electoral systems
Ballot box
Single-winner/majoritarian
Plurality
  • First-past-the-post
  • Plurality at-large (plurality block voting)
  • General ticket (party block voting)

Multi-round voting


Ranked / preferential systems


Cardinal / graded systems

icon Politics portal
  • v
  • t
  • e

Tideman's Alternative Method, also called Alternative Smith or Alternative Schwartz, is an electoral system developed by Nicolaus Tideman which selects a single winner using votes that express preferences.

This method is Smith-efficient, making it a kind of Condorcet method. It uses instant-runoff voting for cycle resolution.

Procedure

Tideman's Alternative Smith with three in the Smith set

The Alternative Smith procedure is as follows:

  1. Eliminate all candidates outside the Smith set.
  2. If there is more than one candidate remaining, eliminate the last-place candidate as in IRV.
  3. Repeat the procedure until there is only one candidate left.

Features

Strategy-resistance

Alternative Smith strongly resists both strategic nomination and strategic voting by political parties or coalitions (although like every system, it can still be manipulated in some situations). The Smith and runoff components of Smith-runoff cover up each other's weaknesses:

  1. Smith-efficient methods are difficult for any coalition to manipulate, because no majority-strength coalition will have an incentive to remove a Condorcet winner: if most voters prefer A to B, A can already defeat B.
    • This reasoning does not apply to situations with a Condorcet cycle, however.
    • While Condorcet cycles are rare in practice with honest voters, burial (ranking a strong rival last, below weak opponents) can often create a false cycle.
  2. Instant runoff voting is resistant to burial, because it is only based on each voter's top preference in any given round. This means that burial strategies effective against the Smith-elimination step are not effective against the instant runoff step.
    • On the other hand, instant-runoff voting is highly vulnerable to a lesser evil (decapitation) strategy: defeating a greater evil requires voters to rank a strong candidate first, rather than express their sincere beliefs.
    • However, if such a candidate exists (with majority support), they will usually be a Condorcet winner, and elected in the first round.

The combination of these two methods creates a highly-resistant system.

Spoiler effects

Alternative Smith fails independence of irrelevant alternatives, meaning it can sometimes be affected by spoiler candidates. However, the method adheres to a weaker property that eliminates most spoilers, sometimes called independence of Smith-dominated alternatives (ISDA). This method states that if one candidate (X) wins an election, and a new alternative (Y) is added, X will still win the election as long as Y is not in the highest-ranked cycle.

Comparison table

The following table compares Alternative Smith with other single-winner election methods:

Comparison of single-winner voting systems
Criterion: Majority Majority loser criterion Mutual majority criterion Condorcet winner[Tn 1] Condorcet loser Smith[Tn 1] ISDA[Tn 1] LIIA IIA[Tn 1] Cloneproof Monotone Participation Later-no-harm[Tn 1] Later-no-help[Tn 1] No favorite betrayal[Tn 1]
Anti-plurality No Yes No No No No No No No No Yes Yes No No Yes
Approval Yes No No No[Tn 2] No Yes Yes Yes Yes[Tn 3] Yes Yes Yes No Yes Yes
Baldwin Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No No No No No No No No
Black Yes Yes No Yes Yes No No No No No Yes No No No No
Borda count No Yes No No Yes No No No No No Yes Yes No Yes No
Bucklin Yes Yes Yes No No No No No No No Yes No No Yes No
Coombs Yes Yes Yes No Yes No No No No No No No No No Yes
Copeland Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No No Yes No No No No
Dodgson Yes No No Yes No No No No No No No No No No No
Highest median Yes Yes[Tn 4] No[Tn 5] No[Tn 2] No No No Yes Yes[Tn 3] Yes Yes No[Tn 6] No Yes Yes
Instant-runoff voting Yes Yes Yes No Yes No No No No Yes No No Yes Yes No
Kemeny–Young Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No Yes No No No No
Minimax Yes No No Yes[Tn 7] No No No No No No Yes No No[Tn 7] No No
Nanson Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No No No No No No No No
Plurality Yes No No No No No No No No No Yes Yes Yes Yes No
Random ballot[Tn 8] No No No No No No No Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes
Ranked pairs Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No Yes Yes No[Tn 6] No No No
Runoff Yes Yes No No Yes No No No No No No No Yes Yes No
Schulze Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No Yes Yes No[Tn 6] No No No
Score No No No No[Tn 2] No No No Yes Yes[Tn 3] Yes Yes Yes No Yes Yes
Sortition[Tn 9] No No No No No No No Yes Yes No Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes
STAR No Yes No No[Tn 2] Yes No No No No No Yes No No No No
Tideman alternative Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No No Yes No No No No No
Table Notes
  1. ^ a b c d e f g |Condorcet, Smith and Independence of Smith-dominated alternatives criteria are incompatible with Independence of irrelevant alternatives, Consistency, Participation, Later-no-harm, Later-no-help, and Favorite betrayal[clarification needed] criteria.
  2. ^ a b c d In Approval, Score, and Majority Judgment, if all voters have perfect information about each other's true preferences, any Majority Condorcet or Majority winner can be strategically forced. In particular if every voter knows that "A or B are the two most-likely to win" and differentiates between the two, then the Condorcet winner, if one exists and is in the set {A,B}, will always win. Laslier, J-F (2006), "Strategic approval voting in a large electorate" (PDF), IDEP Working Papers (405), Marseille, France
  3. ^ a b c Approval voting, score voting, and majority judgment satisfy IIA if it is assumed that voters rate candidates independently using their own absolute scale. For this to hold, in some elections, some voters must use less than their full voting power despite having meaningful preferences among viable candidates.
  4. ^ Majority Judgment may elect a candidate uniquely least-preferred by over half of voters, but it never elects the candidate uniquely bottom-rated by over half of voters.
  5. ^ Majority Judgment fails the mutual majority criterion, but satisfies the criterion if the majority ranks the mutually favored set above a given absolute grade and all others below that grade.
  6. ^ a b c In Highest median, Ranked Pairs, and Schulze voting, there is always a regret-free, semi-honest ballot for any voter, holding all other ballots constant and assuming they know enough about how others will vote. Under such circumstances, there is always at least one way for a voter to participate without grading any less-preferred candidate above any more-preferred one.
  7. ^ a b A variant of Minimax that counts only pairwise opposition, not opposition minus support, fails the Condorcet criterion and meets later-no-harm.
  8. ^ A randomly chosen ballot determines winner. This and closely related methods are of mathematical interest and included here to demonstrate that even unreasonable methods can pass voting method criteria.
  9. ^ Where a winner is randomly chosen from the candidates, sortition is included to demonstrate that even non-voting methods can pass some criteria.


References

  • Green-Armytage, James. Four Condorcet-Hare Hybrid Methods for Single-Winner Elections.
  • v
  • t
  • e
Part of the politics and election series
Single-winner
Proportional
Systems
Allocation
Quotas
Mixed
Criteria
Other
Comparison
PortalProject